Would ‘lottocracy’ be a better form of government than democracy?

444313c

Winston Churchill is attributed with the quote, ‘Democracy is the worst form of government, except for all those others that have been tried.’

But it’s William F. Buckley who said, ‘I am obliged to confess I should sooner live in a society governed by the first two thousand names in the Boston telephone directory than in a society governed by the two thousand faculty members of Harvard University.’

Alex Guerrero, assistant professor of philosophy, medical ethics and health policy at the University of Pennsylvania (and also a law school classmate of mine), thinks Buckley may have been on to something, and he makes the case for selecting representatives not by elections, but through a lottery system in Aeon today:

First, rather than having a single, generalist legislature such as the United States Congress, the legislative function would be fulfilled by many different single-issue legislatures (each one focusing on, for example, just agriculture or health care). There might be 20 or 25 of these single-issue legislatures, perhaps borrowing existing divisions in legislative committees or administrative agencies: agriculture, commerce and consumer protection, education, energy, health and human services, housing and urban development, immigration, labour, transportation, etc.

These single-issue legislatures would be chosen by lottery from the political jurisdiction, with each single-issue legislature consisting of 300 people. Each person chosen would serve for a three-year term. Terms would be staggered so that each year 100 new people begin, and 100 people finish. All adult citizens in the political jurisdiction would be eligible to be selected. People would not be required to serve if selected, but the financial incentive would be significant, efforts would be made to accommodate family and work schedules, and the civic culture might need to be developed so that serving is seen as a significant civic duty and honour.

At first read, it sounds like a nightmare out of an Arthur Miller play.  Three hundred random US citizens would congregate to tackle a discrete issue like climate change, health care reform, or immigration reform.

What’s so bad about democracy? 

Before you dismiss the idea outright, it’s important to bear in mind the long, long list of problems with elections, in their current form in the United States and in other mature democracies — and that’s saying nothing about the question of free and fair elections in countries where democratic institutions are less robust.  The business of policymaking of a typical 21st century government is typically too complex for direct democracy to thrive in most jurisdictions. The need to become informed about the nuances of even major policy decisions would quickly overwhelm all of us.  Experiments with direct democracy, through the proliferation of ballot initiatives to decide key issues, have worked better in some places (Switzerland) than in others (California).  The limitations of direct democracy have meant that, outside the classical era of Athenian democracy and a few referendum-driven jurisdictions, ‘democracy’ for most people today means representative democracy.  Voters elect legislators and executives on the basis of a plethora of policy positions.

Of course, by gaining efficiency, indirect democracies lose precision — voters will choose one candidate over another for many reasons, and no voter’s policy priorities may line up entirely with any candidate.

Moreover, we can see the other problems of representative democracy in modern US politics.  Marketing and advertising, since at least the onset of the television era, can now be more important than policy positions.  Accordingly, representatives spend more time today raising money from donors than tending to the business of lawmaking, undermining the one-person-one-vote principle that undergirds representative democracy.  As Alex notes, the current process is subject to all sorts of problems.  The influence of money and lobbyists can lead to agency and electoral capture.  Collective action problems are rife — interest groups who care deeply about an issue can skew policies to their favor, even at the expense of the widely dispersed gains that might otherwise accrue to the rest of the population.  Protectionism, tariffs and free trade is a classic example.

Gerrymandering, barriers to entry and the advantages of incumbency massively reduce competition within the political marketplace.  It’s left us with a system where, as Alex writes, ’44 per cent of US Congresspersons have a net worth of more than $1 million; 82 per cent are male; 86 per cent are white, and more than half are lawyers or bankers.’ It’s a system where Congressional reelection rates in the United States routinely exceed 90% — even in a massive ‘wave’ election like the 2010 midterms that saw a Republican wave, the reelection rate was still 85%.  Part of that you can blame on gerrymandering, but more so on the natural preferences and geopolitical distribution of urban and rural voters — and perhaps even more so on the US electoral system (i.e., single-member plurality districts instead of proportional representation).  

Tradition, financial and political infrastructure, a first-past-the-post electoral system and path dependence mean that, in the United States, two political parties reign supreme.  When those two parties agree on policy preferences, it means there’s effectively no competition within the political marketplace on many key issues — in the past three decades, this has included drug legislation, foreign policy, national security, military affairs, gun regulation, financial regulation, home ownership policy and other matters.  In many cases, the bipartisan consensus has turned out to be wrong.

Electoral competition, too, is rife with short-term thinking.  In a world where public servants are focused on reelection in two years (the US House of Representatives), four years (the US president) or six years (the US Senate), there will always be a temptation to focus on short-term benefits at the expense of long-term costs.  Say what you want about the People’s Republic of China, but the governing Chinese Communist Party has to contemplate long-term effects of its policies, because there’s no alternative party to blame.  In the US system, Democrats and Republicans can rotate in and out of office and blame each other for perpetuity.  Not so in China — the CCP has to own its policy decisions or face a massive popular revolt.

That all assumes, too, that voters make well-informed, rational decisions.  As Bryan Caplan argues in The Myth of the Rational Voter: How Democracies Choose Bad Policies, borrowing from the insights of economic theory, ‘democracy’ fails primarily due to irrational and ill-informed voters:

In the naive public-interest view, democracy works because it does what voters want.  In the view of most democracy skeptics, it fails because it does not do what voters want.  In my view, democracy fails because it does what voters want.  In economic jargon, democracy has a built-in externality.  An irrational voter does not hurt only himself.  He also hurts everyone who is, as a result of his irrationality, more likely to live under misguided policies.  Since most of the cost of voter irrationality is external — paid for by other people, why not indulge?  If enough voters think this way, socially injurious policies win by popular demand.

It’s also worth asking how truly ‘democratic’ elections have become.  Since the 20th century, government has become so complex that many policy decisions are two steps removed from the ballot box, with legislators ceding control to specialized regulators.  In the United States, the wide-ranging administrative and regulatory state nearly amounts to a fourth, unelected branch of government.  Critics of the European Union have long pointed to a ‘democratic deficit’ within the growing EU institutions.  Despite a growing role for the elected European Parliament and perhaps a more representative era in selecting the European Commission, the key decisions of European integration (including the creation of the single market and monetary union) were made more by treaty than at the ballot box. 

 

So should we, therefore, turn to policymaking-by-lottocracy? 

A turn to sortition

It’s not entirely without basis in either historical or contemporary governance, as Alex notes:

In ancient Athens, the birthplace of democracy, lottery-selection was used to choose political actors in three of its four major governmental institutions. Selection of political officials in late medieval and early renaissance Italy incorporated selection by lot. More recently, Citizens’ Assemblies (in which citizens were chosen at random to serve on the assembly, and in which citizens heard from experts prior to coming up with their own proposals) were used in the Netherlands to reform election law, and in Canada (in British Columbia and Ontario). Randomly chosen citizens were also brought into the process of constitutional reform in Iceland in 2010, but nothing of the scope that I am envisioning has been tried before.

You can add to that list the recent development of the California Citizens Redistricting Commission, which was established in 2009 for the purpose of drawing the borders of legislative districts in the state of California.  The commission is comprised of 14 members — five Democrats, five Republicans and four nonpartisan commissioners.  An applicant review panel, itself randomly selected, narrows the pool of applicants to 60 (20 in each category).  California’s state legislature leaders reduce the pool to 48 (12 in each category), and California’s state auditor randomly draws three Democrats, three Republicans and two nonpartisan members.  Those eight select six additional commissioners from among the remaining applicants.  It remains to be seen how well California’s new approach to redistricting will work.

In the case of Canada’s electoral reform assemblies, voters ultimately rejected by referendum the recommendations of each of the Ontario assembly (mixed-member proportional representation) and the British Columbia assembly (single-transferable vote).  Democracy ultimately vetoed lottocracy.

In the meanwhile, the Icelandic example also demonstrates just how tricky lottocracy would be in a system still dominated by electoral politics.  The ‘crowdsourced constitution’ became a punchline, even in a homogenous country of just 300,000 people, which has a relatively strong civic tradition (Iceland’s parliament, the Alþingi, was founded in AD 930, making it the world’s oldest).  Despite the recommendations of a panel of 25 Icelandic citizens and a six-question referendum, Iceland’s traditional political parties found ways to stymie the constitutional reform process, particularly after the center-right parties responsible for Iceland’s peculiarly spectacular financial crisis returned to power in April 2013.

In some regards, we already have a model for lottocracy — the common-law concept of trial by jury.  We use an essentially random pool of everyday citizens to pluck anywhere from six to 23 people to determine whether to pursue charges against a defendant in the criminal justice system and, once charged, whether the facts of the case prove that the defendant is guilty ‘beyond a reasonable doubt.’  Peremptory strikes and other limitations can skew the composition of juries, however, and criminal research shows that despite the best effort of jury instructions, jurors often can’t avoid bringing their own biases and prejudices to making life-and-death decisions.

But you can look back to early colonial America for a more apposite precedent, as juries were often more powerful than lawmakers in formulating policy.  Though English law, by the 18th century, was already imposing constraints of the power of juries, early US law (especially in Massachusetts) didn’t begin shrinking the role of juries until shortly after the American revolution.  For example, a grand jury would meet several times a year to sort the building of bridges, roads and other infrastructure.  As William E. Nelson writes in Americanization of the Common Law: The Impact of Legal Change on Massachusetts Society, 1760-1830:

The only way for officials to ensure enforcement of the law was to obtain community support for the law, and the best way to obtain that support was to permit local communities to determine the substance of the law through legal institutions such as the jury.

By the early 19th century, judges and a more organized legal profession started clawing back the power of juries in Massachusetts and throughout the United States.  No longer would grand juries set policy and no longer would petit juries be responsible for findings of fact and findings of law, which would henceforth be left to judges and attorneys.  Even today, we have an entire body of law on the rules of evidence, in part because we don’t quite trust juries.  Moreover, sensational cases (e.g., the Trayvon Martin shooting, the subsequent murder trial and all-around media/opinion/cultural pile-up) and statistics on conviction rates for African-Americans reveal deep doubts about whether juries are truly representative on the basis of race, ethnicity, class, gender, age and other vectors.

As Nelson explains, the lawmaking-by-jury phenomenon worked in New England only to the extent of a homogenous society with a shared (or coerced) set of values.  Elements that worked in local legal systems in the Puritan 18th century Massachusetts soon faltered in state and federal legal systems in the more heterogeneous 19th century America.  That might also explain why direct democracy has worked better in Switzerland, a country of eight million people of relatively homogenous ethnicity (if not language), than in California, a state of 38 million people with much more racial and ethnic diversity.

Any 21st century sortition-based system would also face the same criticisms.  Despite any safeguards designed to maximize participation (short of coercion), would the citizen assemblies ultimately skew toward the elderly? Toward the wealthy? Would citizens be better or worse at evading capture from industry players who chiefly have the expertise?  Would a bureaucracy develop to ‘assist’ the citizen assemblies and, if so, what’s to stop it from maximizing its own institutional role and stealing the agenda from the actual citizens à la Sir Humphrey?

Within a decade or two, researchers can examine experiments like the CCRC to determine whether handing power to a randomized citizen’s assembly results in better policy outcomes.  In the meanwhile, there’s nothing to stop policymakers from engaging further experiments with sortition to assess and recommend policies.  Given the growing political polarization that characterizes US electoral politics, sortition might even become a key to unlocking the increasingly dysfunctional channels of policymaking in Washington on the most pressing issues.

 

One thought on “Would ‘lottocracy’ be a better form of government than democracy?”

  1. If democracy (or lottery style) worked, then every corporation, company, and firm, would be run as a democracy. There are very good reasons involving differences in intelligence, knowledge, skills, time, etc which make democratic rule abysmal for all but a few small organizations. The simple existence of asymmetrical abilities to propagandize by one person (or group) versus another (one group has a larger megaphone or all the TV stations), makes the idea of democratic decision making absurd in almost all situations. Democracy (as practiced in the West) has been and continues to be a purposefully designed illusion to control the populations by giving them the sense that they are in control.
    Having this illusionary system hides the true ruling powers from the public eye; which allows the ruling class to face little opposition from the public or other centers of power (military, church, intellectuals, etc) even if the ruling class enacts civilizational destructive policies. In the Chinese system (and all overt ruler systems) it is nearly impossible to enact civilizational destructive policies without the use of extreme violence as the method of coercion.

    We in the West have had a ruling class which has enacted civilization destructive policies. I don’t know when it started and I don’t know exactly who these ruling class folks are/were, but the evidence of the policies is obvious today. The West has a fertility rate far below replacement level (policies caused this), the rulers’ solution is immigration from dissimilar races and cultures, which is without a doubt genocide of the host civilization. The high culture of the West (which contributed more to the world than any other civilization) has been replaced by sexualized degenerative pop culture (policy decisions did this). The positive character traits of Western civilization (honor, honesty, self-policing, hard work, humility, respect for nature, respect for children, respect for women, etc) have all been eroded by policy decisions of the ruling class.

    Chinese leadership (like many leaderships in Asia) are held by the populations to be the protectors of the civilization and the facilitators of the longevity of the civilization. Our democratic systems in the West have produced exactly the opposite result. Our civilization is in decline and most likely terminal with this corrosive system (and the ruling elite it invites) we are saddled with. To travel the great capitals of Europe and experience the marvels of Western civilization, and then to gaze upon the people in the street, you immediately know that something is terminally wrong.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *